1
CRITICAL THINKING: THE VERY BASICS - ANSWERS
Dona Warren, Philosophy Department, The University of Wisconsin – Stevens Point
Argument Recognition, Analysis, and Evaluation
I’ve highlighted important parts of some arguments and my diagrams and comments
are in blue. In order to prevent inadvertent peeking at upcoming diagrams, I’ve put
only one argument on each page of this answer booklet.
Philosophy
Directions: For each of the following passages, determine whether or not it contains
an argument. If a passage does contain an argument, diagram it. You don’t need to
evaluate it.
1) “Studying philosophy helps us to excel in many other areas. Therefore, studying
philosophy is a worthwhile endeavor.”
Notice how the conclusion indicator expression “therefore” helps us to identify the
inference in this argument.
Studying philosophy helps us to excel in many other areas.
Studying philosophy is a worthwhile endeavor.
2
2) “Since philosophy cultivates the use of reason, studying philosophy helps us to
excel in many other areas.”
Notice how the reason indicator expression “since” helps us to identify the inference
in this argument.
Philosophy cultivates the use of reason.
Studying philosophy is a worthwhile endeavor.
3
3) “Studying philosophy is a worthwhile endeavor because philosophy addresses the
most interesting questions that there are.”
Notice how the reason indicator expression “because” helps us to identify the
inference in this argument.
Notice also that, due to the placement of “because” in this passage, the reason
for the conclusion
follows
the conclusion. The passage
first
state the conclusion and
then
states the reason for the conclusion. We might say that the “narrative order” of
the ideas in the passage – a conclusion followed by the reason - is the reverse of the
the “logical order” of these ideas – a reason followed by conclusion. (If you look at
the previous two arguments, you’ll see that the narrative order of the ideas was
identical to the logical order of the ideas, because in both passages, the statement of
the reason for the conclusion preceded the statement of the conclusion.)
It’s important to remember that reason indicator expressions like “because”
and “since” can switch the order like this.
“A therefore B” is ., but “A because B” is .
Studying philosophy is a worthwhile endeavor.
Philosophy addresses the most interesting questions that there are.
A
È
B
B
È
A
4
+
4) “Philosophy addresses the most interesting questions that there are. After all,
philosophy addresses questions that can’t be answered using standard empirical
methods and questions that can’t be answered using standard empirical methods are
always the most interesting.”
Notice how the reason indicator expression “After all” helps us to identify the
inference in this argument, and notice how – as with the previous argument – it shows
us that the reasons follow the conclusion in the passage.
Notice, too, how “and” tells us that the two ideas are added. “And” and similar
expressions (like “moreover,” “furthermore,” “but,” and “however”) often, but not
always, indicate that two ideas are dependent reasons.
Philosophy addresses the most interesting questions that there are.
Philosophy addresses questions that can’t
be answered using standard empirical
methods.
Questions that can’t be answered
using standard empirical methods
are always the most interesting.
5
+
5) “Since philosophy cultivates the use of reason, studying philosophy helps us to
excel in many other areas. Therefore, studying philosophy is a worthwhile endeavor.
Besides, philosophy addresses the most interesting questions that there are. After
all, philosophy addresses questions that can’t be answered using standard empirical
methods and questions that can’t be answered using standard empirical methods are
always the most interesting.”
Notice how “since,” “therefore,” and “after all,” help us to see where the inferences
are. Notice how “and” signals dependent reasons. And notice how “besides” serves to
separate the independent lines of reasoning.
Studying philosophy helps us to excel in
man
y
other areas.
Studying philosophy is a worthwhile endeavor.
Philosophy cultivates the use of reason.
Philosophy addresses the most interesting
questions that there are.
Philosophy addresses
questions that can’t
be answered using
standard empirical
methods.
Questions that can’t
be answered using
standard empirical
methods are always
the most interesting.
6
6) “The nature of philosophy is itself a philosophical question, but I think of
philosophy as the activity of considering questions that can’t be answered empirically
(that is to say, questions that can’t be answered by observation or experiment) and
addressing these questions by thinking rationally, or by employing the sort of critical
thinking skills we’re studying here. The nonempirical questions examined by philosophy
fall into three main categories: 1) epistemology, which considers questions about
knowledge, 2) metaphysics, which considers questions about the ultimate nature of
reality, and 3) value theory, which considers questions about nature of good and bad
as those concepts are invoked in various contexts. The following passages will
introduce you to some of the issues addressed by each branch of philosophy.”
I don’t think that this passage tries to convince us of anything by advancing other
ideas as evidence, so I don’t think that this passage contains an argument.
7
Epistemology
Directions: For each of the following passages, determine whether or not it contains
an argument. If a passage does contain an argument, diagram it, evaluate the
premises, evaluate the inferences, and evaluate the argument as a whole. (Note:
Because these arguments concern fairly abstract material, reasonable people might
disagree about their evaluations.)
7) “Knowledge - as philosophers usually use the term - is justified, true, belief. A
belief is justified if we have good reason to believe it. Beliefs that have some
empirical or rational support, for example, are probably justified. Beliefs that we hold
simply out of fear or superstition, probably aren’t. A belief is true if it corresponds
to reality. My belief that that the earth is nearer to the moon than it is to the sun,
for example, is true if and only if the earth is nearer to the moon than it is to the
sun.”
This passage doesn’t contain an argument because it isn’t trying to convince us of
something by advancing other ideas as evidence. It simply introduces us to
philosophy’s concept of knowledge.
8
8) “Do you know for certain that the objects you see around you are really there? For
all you know, you could be hallucinating every aspect of your experience so you can’t
be certain that anything really exists.”
Notice how the first sentence isn’t important because it doesn’t help to establish the
ultimate conclusion, and notice how the conclusion indicator word “so” helps us to
identify the inference.
This is a version of the argument advanced by René Descartes in Meditation I
of his
Meditations on First Philosophy
.
I think that the inference is pretty good. If one of our beliefs
could
be false
then we can’t be
certain
that it’s true, and if we could be hallucinating everything
then it could be the case that everything around us mere appearance. It could be the
case that nothing exists, and so we can’t be certain that anything does exist.
But what about the premise? Is it true that, for all you know, you could be
hallucinating every aspect of your experience? The following argument attempts to
demonstrate that this premise is false. Let’s see if it works.
For all you know, you could be hallucinating every aspect of your experience.
You can’t be certain that anything really exists.
9
9) “Don’t be silly. I know that I’m not hallucinating every aspect of my experience
because the people around me say I’m not hallucinating.”
Notice how the first sentence isn’t important because it doesn’t help to establish the
ultimate conclusion, and notice how the reason indicator word “because” helps us to
identify the inference.
This argument is seriously flawed, but the flaw (although serious) can be hard
to spot. Can you see what’s wrong?
The problem isn’t with the inference, although it’s easy to think that this is
where the problem lies because it’s easy to think something like, “Okay. Maybe the
people around me say I’m not hallucinating, but who says they’re right? Maybe they’re
mistaken or lying.” The problem with this objection is that although people can be
mistaken or deceptive, we don’t need to worry about trusting what these other people
say in this particular case. The fact that these people
exist
, mistaken or not, is
enough to show that you’re not hallucinating everything. After all, you’re not
hallucinating
them
.
Now do you see what’s wrong with this argument? The problem rests with the
premise. Is it true? Probably. Could people who don’t already believe the ultimate
conclusion believe it? Probably not. People who don’t already believe that they’re not
hallucinating every aspect of their experience must think that they might be
hallucinating every aspect of their experience. Such individuals won’t be sure that
there
are
other people around them; maybe what appear to be other people are simply
hallucinations.
This premise assumes the conclusion. This argument is circular. Can you think
of a noncircular argument for the same conclusion?
The people around me say I’m not hallucinating.
I know that I’m not hallucinating every aspect of my experience.
10
Metaphysics
Directions: For each of the following passages, determine whether or not it contains
an argument. If a passage does contain an argument, diagram it, evaluate the
premises, evaluate the inferences, and evaluate the argument as a whole. (Note:
Because these arguments concern fairly abstract material, reasonable people might
disagree about their evaluations.)
10) “Bad things happen every day, so there can’t be an all-good, all-powerful being in
charge of the universe. Therefore God doesn’t exist. Of course, it’s probably useless
to try to convince devout theists of this.”
Notice how the last sentence isn’t important because it doesn’t help to establish the
ultimate conclusion, and notice how the conclusion indicator words “so” and
“therefore” help us to identify the inferences.
I think that the premise is fine because I think that it’s true and acceptable to
people who don’t already believe that God doesn’t exist.
I also think that the inference from the subconclusion to the ultimate
conclusion is fine because it seems to me that if people believe the subconclusion, it’s
reasonable for them to believe the ultimate conclusion on that basis.
However, I don’t think that the inference from the premise to the
subconclusion is sufficiently strong. Because an all-good, all-powerful being might
have good reason to allow bad things to happen, someone could believe the premise
without believing the subconclusion.
The fact that the inference from the premise to the subconclusion is weak is
enough to make this argument bad.
By the way, this argument is a fairly basic version of the Problem of Evil. More
developed versions of the Problem of Evil attempt to circumvent my criticism by
arguing that a God-like being can’t have a good reason for allowing bad things to
happen.
There can’t be an all-good, all-powerful being in charge of the universe.
God doesn’t exist.
Bad things happen every day.
11
11) “It’s a fact of life that I’m sure you’ve noticed: People who believe in God usually
keep on believing in God and people who don’t believe in God usually keep on not
believing. People who are Christian usually stay Christian and people who are Buddhist
usually remain Buddhist. Have you ever wondered why religious beliefs are so
incredibly hard to change? I think that religious beliefs are hard to change because
such beliefs are usually very important to people, constituting an essential part of
their identity. Such beliefs tend to be very resistant to modification.”
This one is tricky. It might
look
like this is an argument for the conclusion “religious
beliefs are hard to change.” But look again. Is this passage trying to convince us that
religious beliefs are hard to change? Not really. This passage
presupposes
that
religious beliefs are hard to change – it assumes that we already accept this – and it
goes on to
explain why
this is the case. That makes this passage an explanation, not an
argument.
In order to distinguish arguments from explanations, identify the “target” of
the passage. In this case, the target is “religious beliefs are hard to change.” Then
ask, “Is this passage trying to convince me that this idea is true, or does it assume
that I already accept that this idea is true and simply attempt to account for why
things are this way?” If the passage is trying to convince you of the target, it’s an
argument. If the passage is simply trying to account for why the target is true, it’s an
explanation.
12
12) “Many people are tormented by theological doubts, but they needn’t be. It’s clear
that God exists. After all, things in the universe must have been designed by an
intelligent agent because they exhibit an impressive degree of organization.”
Notice how the first sentence isn’t important because it doesn’t help to establish the
ultimate conclusion, and notice how the reason indicator expressions “after all” and
“because” help us to identify the inferences.
I think that the premise is fine because I think that it’s true and acceptable to
people who don’t already believe that God exists.
I also think that the inference from the subconclusion to the ultimate
conclusion is fine because it seems to me that if people believe the subconclusion, it’s
reasonable for them to believe the ultimate conclusion on that basis.
However, I don’t think that the inference from the premise to the
subconclusion is sufficiently strong. Because there are other viable explanations for
the organization mentioned in the premise – evolution by natural selection, for
example – someone could believe the premise without believing the subconclusion.
The fact that the inference from the premise to the subconclusion is weak is
enough to make this argument bad.
By the way, this argument is a fairly weak version of the Teleological Argument
(also known as “The Argument from Design”) for God’s existence. Some versions of
the Teleological Argument aren’t as susceptible to my criticism of the first
inference, because more sophisticated teleological arguments assume that evolution
by natural selection is basically true and maintain that God’s existence is the best
explanation for why the universe is “set up” to allow for natural selection.
Things in the universe must have been designed by an intelligent agent.
God exists. (Or “It’s clear that God exists.”)
Things in the universe exhibit an impressive degree of organization.
13
Value Theory
Directions: For each of the following passages, determine whether or not it contains
an argument. If a passage does contain an argument, diagram it, evaluate the
premises, evaluate the inferences, and evaluate the argument as a whole. (Note:
Because these arguments concern fairly abstract material, reasonable people might
disagree about their evaluations.)
13) “Consequentialist theories maintain that an action is ethical if it serves to produce
certain desirable consequences. Utilitarianism, for example, is a consequentialistist
ethical theory according to which an action is ethical if it maximizes happiness (or
minimizes unhappiness) for the greatest number of people. Deontological ethical
theories, in contrast, assert that an action is ethical if it corresponds to the moral
law, regardless of that action’s tendency to produce any particular effects.”
This passage isn’t trying to convince us of anything by advancing evidence for its
truth. It simply introduces us to two schools of ethics.
14
+
14) “What makes some actions right and other actions wrong? Well, ethics should be
guided by empirical facts about human nature, and everybody wants to be happy.
Consequently, an action is ethical if it produces the greatest happiness for the
greatest number of people.”
Notice how the first sentence isn’t important because it doesn’t help to establish the
ultimate conclusion. Notice also how the conclusion indicator expression
“consequently” helps us to identify the inference and how “and” connects the
dependent reasons.
This is an argument for a type of utilitarianism. In fact, it’s a simplification of
an argument advanced by Jeremy Bentham, one of the fathers of modern
utilitarianism.
The inference in this argument is very strong, so any criticism must focus on
the premises. I think both premises can be challenged. How might you object to the
premise that ethics should be guided by empirical facts about human nature? How
might you object to the premise that everybody wants to be happy? Which premise
do you think is more vulnerable to criticism?
An action is ethical if it produces the greatest happiness for the greatest number.
Ethics should be guided by empirical
facts about human nature.
Everybody wants to be happy.
15
+
15) “Utilitarianism can’t be right because if it were correct then it would be ethical to
kill one innocent person who isn’t making people happy in order to save ten others who
are making people happy. But clearly it’s never ethical to kill an innocent person.”
Notice how the reason indicator expression “because” helps us to identify the
inference and how “but” connects the dependent reasons.
This criticism of utilitarianism has a strong inference. (In fact, this inference
is valid. If the premises are true then the conclusion
must
be true.) Consequently, if
this argument is bad it must fail at one or both of the premises. What do you think
about them? Do you think that it’s always unethical to kill an innocent person? What
about the claim that if utilitarianism were correct then it would be ethical to kill one
innocent person who isn’t making people happy in order to save ten others who are
making people happy?
Actually, the premise “if utilitarianism were correct then it would be ethical to
kill one innocent person who isn’t making people happy in order to save ten others who
are making people happy” probably only applies to one type of utilitarianism – act
utilitarianism – which says that an action is ethical if
it
serves to maximize happiness.
Other types of utilitarianism are a bit more complex. Rule utilitarianism, for
example, says that an action is ethical if it is of a
type
that would maximize happiness
if
generally practiced
. See the difference? Maybe
one particular
killing of one
innocent person would maximize happiness (the morality of that killing aside), but
what about the
general practice
of killing innocent people in order to maximize
happiness? I suspect that this practice would rapidly cultivate an atmosphere of fear
and paranoia, as everyone wonders if they’ll be killed next. Consequently, rule
utilitarianism would maintain that killing one innocent person in order to save then
others would
not
be ethical.
Utilitarianism can’t be right.
If utilitarianism were correct then it would
be ethical to kill one innocent person who
isn’t making people happy in order to save
ten others who are making people happy.
It’s never ethical to kill an
innocent person.
16
Worldviews
Directions: For each of the following passages, determine whether or not it contains
an argument. If a passage does contain an argument, diagram it, evaluate the
premises, evaluate the inferences, and evaluate the argument as a whole. (Note:
Because these arguments concern fairly abstract material, reasonable people might
disagree about their evaluations.)
16) “Our worldview is our fundamental perspective on reality and is defined by our
epistemological, metaphysical, and value-theoretical assumptions. We all have a
worldview, and it’s important to be aware of the worldview that we have. For one
thing, such an awareness makes it possible for us to adjust our worldviews if we so
choose. For another thing, awareness of our own worldview helps us to better
understand the worldviews that other people have.”
Notice that the first sentence isn’t important because it doesn’t give us reason to
believe the ultimate conclusion - although by defining the terms used in the argument
it does help us to understand the ultimate conclusion. Notice also that “for one thing”
and “for another thing” help us to identify the lines of reasoning. And finally notice
that there are no conclusion or reason indicator expressions to help us identify the
inferences. (Sometimes there aren’t.)
I think that both lines of reasoning are good. Of course, that might be what
you’d expect. After all, I’m a philosopher. Worldview examination is a highly
philosophical activity, so isn’t my assessment of this argument necessarily biased?
In general, if someone accepts an ultimate conclusion, should we discount his or
her positive evaluation of the argument? I don’t think so. For one thing, an individual’s
acceptance of the ultimate conclusion might be a
result
of that person’s positive
assessment of the argument, and not the other way around. For another thing, even if
the individual has other reasons to accept the ultimate conclusion, it doesn’t follow
that his or her assessment of the argument is in any way contaminated by that
acceptance – although it might be prudent for us to ensure that the evaluation isn’t
biased.
It’s important to be aware of the worldview that we have.
An awareness of the worldview that we
have makes it possible to adjust our
worldview if we so choose.
Awareness of our own worldview
helps us to better understand the
worldviews that other people have.
17
17) “Thinking about your worldview can make you feel frustrated and confused.
Therefore, it’s best not to think about your worldview. In addition, serious reflection
about your own worldview might encourage you to feel arrogantly superior to people
who don’t engage in such philosophical contemplation.”
Notice how the conclusion indicator expression “therefore” corresponds to the
inference on the left, how “in addition” separates the lines of reasoning, and how no
conclusion or reason indicator expression corresponds to the inference on the right.
Although both of these premises might be true, I think that the inferences
are weak. Just because something might make us frustrated and confused, it doesn’t
follow that we shouldn’t do it. Maybe the worst frustration and confusion is
temporary, and will be followed by overwhelming benefits. Similarly, it might be the
case that we should do things that carry with them the risk of arrogance because
self-reflective and emotionally mature people are usually able to combat that risk and
because a sense of superiority is often temporary anyway, easily (and sometimes
painfully) punctured by evidence that other people are seldom as stupid or
unobservant as arrogant individuals might think.
But what about people who seem to be arrogant for years on end? Common
wisdom has it that these people are basically insecure and that what appears to be
arrogance is actually posturing designed to help them feel better about themselves.
Do you agree? I honestly don’t know, but I do know that whenever I’m tempted to
show off, it’s because I’m feeling threatened or inferior. When I feel basically good
about myself, I don’t need to be right all the time or try to convince people that I’m
brilliant by using big words when smaller words would be clearer or by dismissing
other people’s thoughts as though they were beneath contempt. Because “apparent
arrogance is often a sign of insecurity” is true of me, and because I assume that I’m
basically similar to other people, I conclude that it’s true of other people as well. (Can
you diagram that argument?)
It’s best not to think about your worldview.
Thinking about your worldview
can make you feel frustrated
and confused.
Serious reflection about your own worldview might
encourage you to feel arrogantly superior to people
who don’t engage in such philosophical contemplation.
18
18) “So, what is your worldview? Think for a moment about your epistemological
beliefs. How important is it to you that your beliefs be true? Would you rather be
wrong and happy, or right and miserable? What do you think is the most trustworthy
source of belief? Do you tend to trust your senses, or do you think that sensory
evidence is too prone to error? Now reflect upon your metaphysical beliefs. Do you
think that everything is basically physical, or do you believe in some nonphysical
reality? Do you think that all events, including your own future actions, are
predetermined, or do you believe in free will? Finally, think for a bit about your
perspective on ethics. Do you think that morality is simply a matter of human
convention? A function of the tendency of an action to produce happiness? A matter
of correspondence to a transcendental moral law? Now, finally, ask yourself if all of
these beliefs “fit together.” Do your epistemological beliefs comport with your
metaphysical and ethical assumptions, for example? Is your metaphysics consistent
with your ethics and epistemology? Can your theory of ethics accommodate your
metaphysics and epistemology? What can be said in favor of your worldview? What
can be said against it? How would you try to convince someone to share your
worldview? Would you want to?”
This passage isn’t trying to convince us of anything, so it isn’t an argument.
19
+
Who-Done-It
Directions: For each of the following passages, determine whether or not it contains
an argument. If a passage does contain an argument, diagram it, evaluate the
premises, evaluate the inferences, and evaluate the argument as a whole.
(Note: You may assume that all of the premises are factually true.)
19) “Who killed Dr. Andrews? It must have been her nephew, Mr. Green. He stood to
inherit over a million dollars at the doctor’s death and he needed the money because
he has gambling debts. Besides, Dr. Andrews sabotaged Mr. Green’s run for political
office, so he probably hated her.”
I’ve labeled the inferences to make them easier to discuss. Notice how “besides”
serves to separate the lines of reasoning, how the reason indicator word “because”
corresponds to inference B, how “and” connects the dependent reasons, and how the
conclusion indicator expression “so” corresponds to inference “C.”
The primary problem with this argument, it seems to me, is that inferences B
and D are both weak because they assume that if someone had a motive for doing
something then he or she must have done it. But of course, that’s not true.
Mr. Green killed Dr. Andrews.
Mr. Green stood to
inherit over a million
dollars.
Mr. Green needs the
money.
Mr. Green has
gambling debts.
Dr Andrews sabotaged
Mr. Green’s run for
political office.
Mr. Green probably
hated Dr. Andrews.
D
C
B
A
20
20) “Haven’t you heard to the story? Just as Mr. Green was ahead in the polls, almost
certain to be elected mayor, Dr. Andrews went to the papers about his gambling
problem. It was front-page news for days, and of course Mr. Green’s campaign was a
lost cause after that. Naturally, there was extensive speculation about why Dr.
Andrews would have behaved so treacherously toward her own nephew, but I think
that she was simply being civic-minded. Dr. Andrews went to the paper because she
honestly believed that Mr. Green would have been a disastrous mayor.”
This isn’t it argument because it doesn’t try to convince us of anything. It does,
however, offer an explanation for Dr. Andrews’ behavior.
21
+
+
21) “Dr. Andrews was poisoned by a little-known and highly-volatile substance.
Consequently, her assassin must have possessed a fairly sophisticated knowledge of
chemistry. Mr. Green, however, has very limited chemical knowledge, so he couldn’t
possibly be the murderer. Additionally, the poison was added to Dr. Andrews’ after-
dinner tea, which proves that whoever killed Dr. Andrews must have been with her in
her home that evening. Mr. Green was attending a law-school reunion over two
hundred miles away from Dr. Andrews’ residence.”
Once again, I’ve labeled the inferences to make them easier to discuss. Notice how
“additionally” serves to separate the lines of reasoning, how the conclusion indicator
word “consequently” corresponds to inference A, how the conclusion indicator word
“so” corresponds to inference B, and how the conclusion indicator expression “which
proves that” corresponds to inference C.
I actually think that this argument is pretty good (assuming, for the sake of
discussion, that the premises are true). And because I think that this argument is
good, I believe the conclusion and am prepared to vindicate Mr. Green.
Mr. Green didn’t kill Dr. Andrews.
Dr. Andrews was
poisoned by a little
known and highly
volatile substance.
Her assassin must
have possessed a
fairly
sophisticated
knowledge of
chemistr
y
.
Mr. Green has
very limited
chemical
knowledge.
The poison was
added to Dr.
Andrews’ after-
dinner tea.
Whoever killed
Dr. Andrews must
have been with
her in her home
that evening.
Mr. Green was
attending a law-
school reunion
over two hundred
miles away from
Dr. Andrews’
residence.
A
B
C
D
22
Argument Construction
Directions: Answer the following questions to fill in the boxes in the diagram on the
next page.
22) Let’s consider the question “Do parrots make good pets?” The answers will be:
“Parrots make good pets,” and “Parrots don’t make good pets.” Choose one of these
answers. (It doesn’t need to be the answer you really believe.) This will be your
ultimate conclusion. Write your ultimate conclusion in the box labeled “U”. (I know
this isn’t a particularly “deep” subject. Sometimes fairly concrete issues are the best
for practicing argument construction.)
23) Think of
one
reason to believe your ultimate conclusion. It doesn’t need to be a
reason you really believe, but it should be something such that if someone
did
believe
it, he’d be rather likely – although probably not compelled - to believe your ultimate
conclusion. Write that in the box labeled “S.”
24) Now look what your wrote in the box labeled “S,” and think of one reason to
believe
that
. (Don’t even
look
at your ultimate conclusion right now. Look only at your
S. Pretend that your U isn’t even there.) Again, it doesn’t need to be a reason you
believe, but it should be something such that that if someone
did
believe it, she’d be
rather likely – although probably not compelled – to believe S. Write that in the box
labeled “P1.”
25) Now look at the inference between S and U. (Don’t look at your P1. Forget about
your P1. Act like P1 isn’t there.) If someone believed S, what else would she need to
believe in order to be
forced
to believe U? Write that in the box labeled “P2.”
26) Now look at what you’ve written. What’s the “theme” of your argument so far?
Are you talking about companionship, for example? Cost? Think of one reason to
believe your ultimate conclusion that has a completely different theme. Again, it
doesn’t need to be anything you actually believe. Write that in the box labeled “P3.”
23
27) Write a passage containing this argument by filling in your ideas in the following
template: “P1 so S. And P2. Therefore U. Besides, P3.”
“Parrots can talk so parrots can entertain you. And animals that can entertain you
make good pets. Therefore parrots make good pets. Besides, parrots don’t need to go
on walks.”
P3. Parrots don’t need to
go on walks.
P1. Parrots can talk.
P2. Animals that
can entertain you
make good pets.
S. Parrots can
entertain you.
U. Parrots make good pets.
+
24
Real Life
Congratulations! You’ve had a reasonable amount of practice recognizing, analyzing,
evaluating, and constructing arguments. Now you can try your skills in the “real world.”
Two factors that can make argument analysis and evaluation difficult are
length and abstraction.
I’d recommend starting with small arguments of one or two paragraphs
concerning reasonably concrete matters (current events, etc.). Letters to the editor
are good places to look.
When you feel reasonably confident, work your way up to arguments presented
in a page or two, but don’t look at material that’s too abstract yet. Unless you’re
studying philosophy or theology, I’d steer away from those arguments for a bit. Look
for articles in magazines and newspapers.
After you’re comfortable analyzing and evaluating the arguments conveyed in
multiple pages in newspaper or magazine articles, feel free to branch out to more
abstract content. Take on Plato, or the free-will debate. But if you find yourself
getting frustrated, go back to simpler, more concrete arguments for a bit. This will
reassure you that the problems you face stem from the difficulty of the material
you’re studying and not from any lack of technical skill on your part.
Have fun!